The illusion of consciousness | Dan Dennett

1,718,229 views ・ 2007-05-03

TED


Please double-click on the English subtitles below to play the video.

00:26
So I'm going to speak about a problem that I have
0
26000
3000
00:29
and that's that I'm a philosopher.
1
29000
3000
00:32
(Laughter)
2
32000
2000
00:34
When I go to a party and people ask me what do I do
3
34000
3000
00:37
and I say, "I'm a professor," their eyes glaze over.
4
37000
5000
00:42
When I go to an academic cocktail party
5
42000
2000
00:44
and there are all the professors around, they ask me what field I'm in
6
44000
4000
00:48
and I say, "philosophy" -- their eyes glaze over.
7
48000
3000
00:51
(Laughter)
8
51000
2000
00:53
When I go to a philosopher's party
9
53000
3000
00:56
(Laughter)
10
56000
3000
00:59
and they ask me what I work on and I say, "consciousness,"
11
59000
4000
01:03
their eyes don't glaze over -- their lips curl into a snarl.
12
63000
5000
01:08
(Laughter)
13
68000
1000
01:09
And I get hoots of derision and cackles and growls
14
69000
6000
01:15
because they think, "That's impossible! You can't explain consciousness."
15
75000
5000
01:20
The very chutzpah of somebody thinking
16
80000
2000
01:22
that you could explain consciousness is just out of the question.
17
82000
4000
01:26
My late, lamented friend Bob Nozick, a fine philosopher,
18
86000
4000
01:30
in one of his books, "Philosophical Explanations,"
19
90000
4000
01:34
is commenting on the ethos of philosophy --
20
94000
5000
01:39
the way philosophers go about their business.
21
99000
2000
01:41
And he says, you know, "Philosophers love rational argument."
22
101000
4000
01:45
And he says, "It seems as if the ideal argument
23
105000
2000
01:47
for most philosophers is you give your audience the premises
24
107000
6000
01:53
and then you give them the inferences and the conclusion,
25
113000
5000
01:58
and if they don't accept the conclusion, they die.
26
118000
4000
02:02
Their heads explode." The idea is to have an argument
27
122000
3000
02:05
that is so powerful that it knocks out your opponents.
28
125000
4000
02:09
But in fact that doesn't change people's minds at all.
29
129000
3000
02:12
It's very hard to change people's minds
30
132000
1000
02:13
about something like consciousness,
31
133000
2000
02:15
and I finally figured out the reason for that.
32
135000
5000
02:20
The reason for that is that everybody's an expert on consciousness.
33
140000
4000
02:24
We heard the other day that everybody's got a strong opinion about video games.
34
144000
4000
02:28
They all have an idea for a video game, even if they're not experts.
35
148000
3000
02:31
But they don't consider themselves experts on video games;
36
151000
3000
02:34
they've just got strong opinions.
37
154000
1000
02:35
I'm sure that people here who work on, say, climate change
38
155000
5000
02:40
and global warming, or on the future of the Internet,
39
160000
5000
02:45
encounter people who have very strong opinions
40
165000
2000
02:47
about what's going to happen next.
41
167000
3000
02:50
But they probably don't think of these opinions as expertise.
42
170000
4000
02:54
They're just strongly held opinions.
43
174000
2000
02:56
But with regard to consciousness, people seem to think,
44
176000
4000
03:00
each of us seems to think, "I am an expert.
45
180000
3000
03:03
Simply by being conscious, I know all about this."
46
183000
3000
03:06
And so, you tell them your theory and they say,
47
186000
2000
03:08
"No, no, that's not the way consciousness is!
48
188000
1000
03:09
No, you've got it all wrong."
49
189000
2000
03:11
And they say this with an amazing confidence.
50
191000
4000
03:15
And so what I'm going to try to do today
51
195000
2000
03:17
is to shake your confidence. Because I know the feeling --
52
197000
3000
03:20
I can feel it myself.
53
200000
2000
03:22
I want to shake your confidence that you know your own innermost minds --
54
202000
6000
03:28
that you are, yourselves, authoritative about your own consciousness.
55
208000
5000
03:33
That's the order of the day here.
56
213000
3000
03:36
Now, this nice picture shows a thought-balloon, a thought-bubble.
57
216000
3000
03:39
I think everybody understands what that means.
58
219000
2000
03:41
That's supposed to exhibit the stream of consciousness.
59
221000
3000
03:44
This is my favorite picture of consciousness that's ever been done.
60
224000
2000
03:46
It's a Saul Steinberg of course -- it was a New Yorker cover.
61
226000
3000
03:49
And this fellow here is looking at the painting by Braque.
62
229000
5000
03:54
That reminds him of the word baroque, barrack, bark, poodle,
63
234000
4000
03:58
Suzanne R. -- he's off to the races.
64
238000
2000
04:00
There's a wonderful stream of consciousness here
65
240000
4000
04:04
and if you follow it along, you learn a lot about this man.
66
244000
4000
04:08
What I particularly like about this picture, too,
67
248000
2000
04:10
is that Steinberg has rendered the guy
68
250000
2000
04:12
in this sort of pointillist style.
69
252000
3000
04:15
Which reminds us, as Rod Brooks was saying yesterday:
70
255000
3000
04:18
what we are, what each of us is -- what you are, what I am --
71
258000
4000
04:22
is approximately 100 trillion little cellular robots.
72
262000
6000
04:28
That's what we're made of.
73
268000
2000
04:30
No other ingredients at all. We're just made of cells, about 100 trillion of them.
74
270000
4000
04:34
Not a single one of those cells is conscious;
75
274000
2000
04:36
not a single one of those cells knows who you are, or cares.
76
276000
5000
04:41
Somehow, we have to explain
77
281000
2000
04:43
how when you put together teams, armies, battalions
78
283000
4000
04:47
of hundreds of millions of little robotic unconscious cells --
79
287000
4000
04:51
not so different really from a bacterium, each one of them --
80
291000
4000
04:55
the result is this. I mean, just look at it.
81
295000
4000
04:59
The content -- there's color, there's ideas, there's memories,
82
299000
4000
05:03
there's history. And somehow all that content of consciousness
83
303000
4000
05:07
is accomplished by the busy activity of those hoards of neurons.
84
307000
5000
05:12
How is that possible? Many people just think it isn't possible at all.
85
312000
4000
05:16
They think, "No, there can't be any
86
316000
2000
05:18
sort of naturalistic explanation of consciousness."
87
318000
4000
05:22
This is a lovely book by a friend of mine named Lee Siegel,
88
322000
3000
05:25
who's a professor of religion, actually, at the University of Hawaii,
89
325000
3000
05:28
and he's an expert magician, and an expert
90
328000
2000
05:30
on the street magic of India, which is what this book is about,
91
330000
4000
05:34
"Net of Magic."
92
334000
2000
05:36
And there's a passage in it which I would love to share with you.
93
336000
3000
05:39
It speaks so eloquently to the problem.
94
339000
6000
05:45
"'I'm writing a book on magic,' I explain, and I'm asked, 'Real magic?'
95
345000
5000
05:50
By 'real magic,' people mean miracles,
96
350000
2000
05:52
thaumaturgical acts, and supernatural powers.
97
352000
2000
05:54
'No,' I answer. 'Conjuring tricks, not real magic.'
98
354000
4000
05:58
'Real magic,' in other words, refers to the magic that is not real;
99
358000
4000
06:02
while the magic that is real, that can actually be done, is not real magic."
100
362000
5000
06:07
(Laughter)
101
367000
4000
06:11
Now, that's the way a lot of people feel about consciousness.
102
371000
4000
06:15
(Laughter)
103
375000
1000
06:16
Real consciousness is not a bag of tricks.
104
376000
2000
06:18
If you're going to explain this as a bag of tricks,
105
378000
2000
06:20
then it's not real consciousness, whatever it is.
106
380000
3000
06:23
And, as Marvin said, and as other people have said,
107
383000
6000
06:29
"Consciousness is a bag of tricks."
108
389000
3000
06:32
This means that a lot of people are just left completely dissatisfied
109
392000
5000
06:37
and incredulous when I attempt to explain consciousness.
110
397000
3000
06:40
So this is the problem. So I have to
111
400000
3000
06:43
do a little bit of the sort of work
112
403000
3000
06:46
that a lot of you won't like,
113
406000
4000
06:50
for the same reason that you don't like to see
114
410000
2000
06:52
a magic trick explained to you.
115
412000
2000
06:54
How many of you here, if somebody -- some smart aleck --
116
414000
4000
06:58
starts telling you how a particular magic trick is done,
117
418000
3000
07:01
you sort of want to block your ears and say, "No, no, I don't want to know!
118
421000
3000
07:04
Don't take the thrill of it away. I'd rather be mystified.
119
424000
3000
07:07
Don't tell me the answer."
120
427000
3000
07:10
A lot of people feel that way about consciousness, I've discovered.
121
430000
3000
07:13
And I'm sorry if I impose some clarity, some understanding on you.
122
433000
6000
07:19
You'd better leave now if you don't want to know some of these tricks.
123
439000
5000
07:24
But I'm not going to explain it all to you.
124
444000
4000
07:28
I'm going to do what philosophers do.
125
448000
3000
07:31
Here's how a philosopher explains the sawing-the-lady-in-half trick.
126
451000
6000
07:37
You know the sawing-the-lady-in-half trick?
127
457000
2000
07:39
The philosopher says, "I'm going to explain to you how that's done.
128
459000
4000
07:43
You see, the magician doesn't really saw the lady in half."
129
463000
5000
07:48
(Laughter)
130
468000
2000
07:50
"He merely makes you think that he does."
131
470000
4000
07:54
And you say, "Yes, and how does he do that?"
132
474000
1000
07:55
He says, "Oh, that's not my department, I'm sorry."
133
475000
2000
07:57
(Laughter)
134
477000
5000
08:02
So now I'm going to illustrate how philosophers explain consciousness.
135
482000
3000
08:05
But I'm going to try to also show you
136
485000
3000
08:08
that consciousness isn't quite as marvelous --
137
488000
3000
08:11
your own consciousness isn't quite as wonderful --
138
491000
2000
08:13
as you may have thought it is.
139
493000
2000
08:15
This is something, by the way, that Lee Siegel talks about in his book.
140
495000
4000
08:19
He marvels at how he'll do a magic show, and afterwards
141
499000
4000
08:23
people will swear they saw him do X, Y, and Z. He never did those things.
142
503000
4000
08:27
He didn't even try to do those things.
143
507000
2000
08:29
People's memories inflate what they think they saw.
144
509000
4000
08:33
And the same is true of consciousness.
145
513000
3000
08:36
Now, let's see if this will work. All right. Let's just watch this.
146
516000
7000
08:43
Watch it carefully.
147
523000
1000
08:56
I'm working with a young computer-animator documentarian
148
536000
3000
08:59
named Nick Deamer, and this is a little demo that he's done for me,
149
539000
5000
09:04
part of a larger project some of you may be interested in.
150
544000
3000
09:07
We're looking for a backer.
151
547000
3000
09:10
It's a feature-length documentary on consciousness.
152
550000
4000
09:14
OK, now, you all saw what changed, right?
153
554000
2000
09:20
How many of you noticed that every one of those squares changed color?
154
560000
5000
09:25
Every one. I'll just show you by running it again.
155
565000
4000
09:34
Even when you know that they're all going to change color,
156
574000
5000
09:39
it's very hard to notice. You have to really concentrate
157
579000
4000
09:43
to pick up any of the changes at all.
158
583000
3000
09:46
Now, this is an example -- one of many --
159
586000
5000
09:51
of a phenomenon that's now being studied quite a bit.
160
591000
2000
09:53
It's one that I predicted in the last page or two of my
161
593000
4000
09:57
1991 book, "Consciousness Explained,"
162
597000
2000
09:59
where I said if you did experiments of this sort,
163
599000
3000
10:02
you'd find that people were unable to pick up really large changes.
164
602000
3000
10:05
If there's time at the end,
165
605000
2000
10:07
I'll show you the much more dramatic case.
166
607000
3000
10:10
Now, how can it be that there are all those changes going on,
167
610000
5000
10:15
and that we're not aware of them?
168
615000
3000
10:18
Well, earlier today, Jeff Hawkins mentioned the way your eye saccades,
169
618000
5000
10:23
the way your eye moves around three or four times a second.
170
623000
3000
10:26
He didn't mention the speed. Your eye is constantly in motion,
171
626000
3000
10:29
moving around, looking at eyes, noses, elbows,
172
629000
3000
10:32
looking at interesting things in the world.
173
632000
2000
10:34
And where your eye isn't looking,
174
634000
2000
10:36
you're remarkably impoverished in your vision.
175
636000
3000
10:39
That's because the foveal part of your eye,
176
639000
3000
10:42
which is the high-resolution part,
177
642000
2000
10:44
is only about the size of your thumbnail held at arms length.
178
644000
3000
10:47
That's the detail part.
179
647000
2000
10:49
It doesn't seem that way, does it?
180
649000
3000
10:52
It doesn't seem that way, but that's the way it is.
181
652000
2000
10:54
You're getting in a lot less information than you think.
182
654000
4000
10:58
Here's a completely different effect. This is a painting by Bellotto.
183
658000
6000
11:04
It's in the museum in North Carolina.
184
664000
2000
11:06
Bellotto was a student of Canaletto's.
185
666000
3000
11:09
And I love paintings like that --
186
669000
1000
11:10
the painting is actually about as big as it is right here.
187
670000
4000
11:14
And I love Canalettos, because Canaletto has this fantastic detail,
188
674000
3000
11:17
and you can get right up
189
677000
3000
11:20
and see all the details on the painting.
190
680000
3000
11:23
And I started across the hall in North Carolina,
191
683000
5000
11:28
because I thought it was probably a Canaletto,
192
688000
2000
11:30
and would have all that in detail.
193
690000
2000
11:32
And I noticed that on the bridge there, there's a lot of people --
194
692000
3000
11:35
you can just barely see them walking across the bridge.
195
695000
3000
11:38
And I thought as I got closer
196
698000
1000
11:39
I would be able to see all the detail of most people,
197
699000
3000
11:42
see their clothes, and so forth.
198
702000
2000
11:44
And as I got closer and closer, I actually screamed.
199
704000
4000
11:48
I yelled out because when I got closer,
200
708000
2000
11:50
I found the detail wasn't there at all.
201
710000
4000
11:54
There were just little artfully placed blobs of paint.
202
714000
4000
11:58
And as I walked towards the picture,
203
718000
3000
12:01
I was expecting detail that wasn't there.
204
721000
3000
12:04
The artist had very cleverly suggested people and clothes
205
724000
5000
12:09
and wagons and all sorts of things,
206
729000
3000
12:12
and my brain had taken the suggestion.
207
732000
3000
12:15
You're familiar with a more recent technology, which is -- There,
208
735000
6000
12:21
you can get a better view of the blobs.
209
741000
2000
12:23
See, when you get close
210
743000
2000
12:25
they're really just blobs of paint.
211
745000
5000
12:30
You will have seen something like this -- this is the reverse effect.
212
750000
6000
12:44
I'll just give that to you one more time.
213
764000
3000
12:47
Now, what does your brain do when it takes the suggestion?
214
767000
7000
12:54
When an artful blob of paint or two, by an artist,
215
774000
5000
12:59
suggests a person -- say, one of
216
779000
6000
13:05
Marvin Minsky's little society of mind --
217
785000
2000
13:07
do they send little painters out to fill in all the details in your brain somewhere?
218
787000
5000
13:12
I don't think so. Not a chance. But then, how on Earth is it done?
219
792000
5000
13:17
Well, remember the philosopher's explanation of the lady?
220
797000
5000
13:22
It's the same thing.
221
802000
3000
13:25
The brain just makes you think that it's got the detail there.
222
805000
3000
13:28
You think the detail's there, but it isn't there.
223
808000
3000
13:31
The brain isn't actually putting the detail in your head at all.
224
811000
3000
13:34
It's just making you expect the detail.
225
814000
3000
13:37
Let's just do this experiment very quickly.
226
817000
3000
13:40
Is the shape on the left the same as the shape on the right, rotated?
227
820000
5000
13:45
Yes.
228
825000
2000
13:47
How many of you did it by rotating the one on the left
229
827000
2000
13:49
in your mind's eye, to see if it matched up with the one on the right?
230
829000
3000
13:52
How many of you rotated the one on the right? OK.
231
832000
4000
13:56
How do you know that's what you did?
232
836000
2000
13:58
(Laughter)
233
838000
3000
14:01
There's in fact been a very interesting debate
234
841000
2000
14:03
raging for over 20 years in cognitive science --
235
843000
3000
14:06
various experiments started by Roger Shepherd,
236
846000
2000
14:08
who measured the angular velocity of rotation of mental images.
237
848000
5000
14:13
Yes, it's possible to do that.
238
853000
2000
14:15
But the details of the process are still in significant controversy.
239
855000
7000
14:22
And if you read that literature, one of the things
240
862000
3000
14:25
that you really have to come to terms with is
241
865000
3000
14:28
even when you're the subject in the experiment, you don't know.
242
868000
2000
14:30
You don't know how you do it.
243
870000
2000
14:32
You just know that you have certain beliefs.
244
872000
3000
14:35
And they come in a certain order, at a certain time.
245
875000
3000
14:38
And what explains the fact that that's what you think?
246
878000
2000
14:40
Well, that's where you have to go backstage and ask the magician.
247
880000
4000
14:44
This is a figure that I love: Bradley, Petrie, and Dumais.
248
884000
4000
14:48
You may think that I've cheated,
249
888000
2000
14:50
that I've put a little whiter-than-white boundary there.
250
890000
5000
14:55
How many of you see that sort of boundary,
251
895000
2000
14:57
with the Necker cube floating in front of the circles?
252
897000
3000
15:00
Can you see it?
253
900000
2000
15:02
Well, you know, in effect, the boundary's really there, in a certain sense.
254
902000
5000
15:07
Your brain is actually computing that boundary,
255
907000
3000
15:10
the boundary that goes right there.
256
910000
5000
15:15
But now, notice there are two ways of seeing the cube, right?
257
915000
2000
15:17
It's a Necker cube.
258
917000
2000
15:19
Everybody can see the two ways of seeing the cube? OK.
259
919000
4000
15:23
Can you see the four ways of seeing the cube?
260
923000
4000
15:27
Because there's another way of seeing it.
261
927000
2000
15:29
If you're seeing it as a cube floating in front of some circles,
262
929000
3000
15:32
some black circles, there's another way of seeing it.
263
932000
3000
15:35
As a cube, on a black background,
264
935000
2000
15:37
as seen through a piece of Swiss cheese.
265
937000
2000
15:39
(Laughter)
266
939000
3000
15:42
Can you get it? How many of you can't get it? That'll help.
267
942000
6000
15:48
(Laughter)
268
948000
2000
15:50
Now you can get it. These are two very different phenomena.
269
950000
5000
15:55
When you see the cube one way, behind the screen,
270
955000
6000
16:01
those boundaries go away.
271
961000
2000
16:03
But there's still a sort of filling in, as we can tell if we look at this.
272
963000
5000
16:08
We don't have any trouble seeing the cube, but where does the color change?
273
968000
4000
16:12
Does your brain have to send little painters in there?
274
972000
3000
16:15
The purple-painters and the green-painters
275
975000
2000
16:17
fight over who's going to paint that bit behind the curtain? No.
276
977000
3000
16:20
Your brain just lets it go. The brain doesn't need to fill that in.
277
980000
4000
16:29
When I first started talking about
278
989000
3000
16:32
the Bradley, Petrie, Dumais example that you just saw --
279
992000
4000
16:36
I'll go back to it, this one --
280
996000
4000
16:40
I said that there was no filling-in behind there.
281
1000000
7000
16:47
And I supposed that that was just a flat truth, always true.
282
1007000
3000
16:50
But Rob Van Lier has recently shown that it isn't.
283
1010000
5000
16:55
Now, if you think you see some pale yellow --
284
1015000
5000
17:00
I'll run this a few more times.
285
1020000
2000
17:02
Look in the gray areas,
286
1022000
4000
17:06
and see if you seem to see something sort of shadowy moving in there --
287
1026000
5000
17:11
yeah, it's amazing. There's nothing there. It's no trick.
288
1031000
7000
17:18
["Failure to Detect Changes in Scenes" slide]
289
1038000
6000
17:24
This is Ron Rensink's work, which was in some degree
290
1044000
2000
17:26
inspired by that suggestion right at the end of the book.
291
1046000
4000
17:30
Let me just pause this for a second if I can.
292
1050000
2000
17:32
This is change-blindness.
293
1052000
2000
17:34
What you're going to see is two pictures,
294
1054000
2000
17:36
one of which is slightly different from the other.
295
1056000
2000
17:38
You see here the red roof and the gray roof,
296
1058000
3000
17:41
and in between them there will be a mask,
297
1061000
2000
17:43
which is just a blank screen, for about a quarter of a second.
298
1063000
4000
17:47
So you'll see the first picture, then a mask,
299
1067000
2000
17:49
then the second picture, then a mask.
300
1069000
2000
17:51
And this will just continue, and your job as the subject
301
1071000
4000
17:55
is to press the button when you see the change.
302
1075000
3000
17:58
So, show the original picture for 240 milliseconds. Blank.
303
1078000
8000
18:06
Show the next picture for 240 milliseconds. Blank.
304
1086000
6000
18:12
And keep going, until the subject presses the button, saying,
305
1092000
4000
18:16
"I see the change."
306
1096000
2000
18:18
So now we're going to be subjects in the experiment.
307
1098000
3000
18:21
We're going to start easy. Some examples.
308
1101000
9000
18:30
No trouble there.
309
1110000
2000
18:32
Can everybody see? All right.
310
1112000
3000
18:35
Indeed, Rensink's subjects took only a little bit more
311
1115000
4000
18:39
than a second to press the button.
312
1119000
2000
18:46
Can you see that one?
313
1126000
1000
18:55
2.9 seconds.
314
1135000
2000
19:04
How many don't see it still?
315
1144000
3000
19:07
What's on the roof of that barn?
316
1147000
2000
19:09
(Laughter)
317
1149000
3000
19:20
It's easy.
318
1160000
2000
19:46
Is it a bridge or a dock?
319
1186000
2000
19:52
There are a few more really dramatic ones, and then I'll close.
320
1192000
4000
19:56
I want you to see a few that are particularly striking.
321
1196000
4000
20:00
This one because it's so large and yet it's pretty hard to see.
322
1200000
7000
20:07
Can you see it?
323
1207000
3000
20:10
Audience: Yes.
324
1210000
2000
20:12
Dan Dennett: See the shadows going back and forth? Pretty big.
325
1212000
3000
20:23
So 15.5 seconds is the median time
326
1223000
4000
20:27
for subjects in his experiment there.
327
1227000
2000
20:29
I love this one. I'll end with this one,
328
1229000
3000
20:32
just because it's such an obvious and important thing.
329
1232000
3000
20:37
How many still don't see it? How many still don't see it?
330
1237000
6000
20:43
How many engines on the wing of that Boeing?
331
1243000
3000
20:46
(Laughter)
332
1246000
1000
20:47
Right in the middle of the picture!
333
1247000
6000
20:53
Thanks very much for your attention.
334
1253000
1000
20:54
What I wanted to show you is that scientists,
335
1254000
5000
20:59
using their from-the-outside, third-person methods,
336
1259000
4000
21:03
can tell you things about your own consciousness
337
1263000
2000
21:05
that you would never dream of,
338
1265000
2000
21:07
and that, in fact, you're not the authority
339
1267000
2000
21:09
on your own consciousness that you think you are.
340
1269000
2000
21:11
And we're really making a lot of progress
341
1271000
2000
21:13
on coming up with a theory of mind.
342
1273000
3000
21:16
Jeff Hawkins, this morning, was describing his attempt
343
1276000
6000
21:22
to get theory, and a good, big theory, into the neuroscience.
344
1282000
4000
21:26
And he's right. This is a problem.
345
1286000
5000
21:31
Harvard Medical School once -- I was at a talk --
346
1291000
2000
21:33
director of the lab said, "In our lab, we have a saying.
347
1293000
4000
21:37
If you work on one neuron, that's neuroscience.
348
1297000
3000
21:40
If you work on two neurons, that's psychology."
349
1300000
3000
21:43
(Laughter)
350
1303000
4000
21:47
We have to have more theory, and it can come as much from the top down.
351
1307000
3000
21:50
Thank you very much.
352
1310000
2000
21:52
(Applause)
353
1312000
4000
About this website

This site will introduce you to YouTube videos that are useful for learning English. You will see English lessons taught by top-notch teachers from around the world. Double-click on the English subtitles displayed on each video page to play the video from there. The subtitles scroll in sync with the video playback. If you have any comments or requests, please contact us using this contact form.

https://forms.gle/WvT1wiN1qDtmnspy7